WOUTER PEETERS
  • Home
  • About Me
  • Research topics
  • Publications
  • Public Engagement (English)
  • Publiek Engagement (Nederlands)
  • Contact
  • Placement-based learning




​Public Engagement

To Strike or Disrupt? (take 2)

2/17/2020

0 Comments

 
On the occasion of the strike in November-December 2019, Liam Shields wrote a post To Strike or Disrupt on whether or not people on research leave should go on strike, since their withdrawing of their labour does not cause much disruption to normal proceedings. 

Liam argued that on the basis of the principle of maximising disruption, these people should, rather than work to contract and donate their salary to the fighting fund, which enables colleagues in precarious positions to go on strike. 

On the occasion of the upcoming strike (February-March 2020), it seemed appropriate to me to recall Liam's argument and to flesh out some implications and worries a bit further. 

​You can read my full post on Justice Everywhere. 
0 Comments

Can we solve the dilemma between pursuing personal projects and the demands of morality by limiting the scope of morality?

2/3/2020

0 Comments

 
In this post for Justice Everywhere, I engaging with some of the fascinating ideas discussed by Samuel Scheffler in his 1986 article Morality’s demands and their limits and his 1992 book Human morality. His observations and questions do not seem to leave me at peace and require much further reflection.

Pursuing our personal, valuable projects often conflicts with requirements of morality. One way to solve this dilemma is to limit the scope of morality by excluding certain areas of life or activities from moral assessment and holding that moral demands do not apply to them. I argue, building on Scheffler's diagnosis, that such strategies remain unsuccessful. Morality appears to be pervasive. It pervades all areas of life. So we have to look elsewhere to solve the dilemma - by evaluating acts, their impacts, theor context, alternatives, and the agents involved. 

Please visit Justice Everywhere to read the full post. 

0 Comments

Are 'New Harms' really all that new?

7/1/2019

0 Comments

 
Some theorists argue that contemporary problems such as climate change, sweatshop labour, biodiversity loss, … are New Harms – they are unprecedented problems, and differ in important respects from more familiar harms. Intuitively, this view seems to make sense, but in this blog post for Justice Everywhere I argue that this view is mistaken.

I’ll briefly discuss slavery and the depletion of the ozone layer as examples and then go on to discuss some lessons we can draw from these analogies.

For example, one of the problems that renders climate change so much harder to tackle than the depletion of the ozone layer is the much deeper entrenchment of greenhouse gases. In contrast to substances that deplete ozone layer (which were used in a limited number of applications), greenhouse gases are the by-product of virtually any human activity, and our economy quite frankly relies on them. However, consider the analogy with slavery: at some point, slavery was entirely accepted throughout the world and seemed essential to the economies of Great Britain and the USA. Despite this entrenchment, the British were highly committed to dismantling their slave trade and to persuading other nations to do the same. This is encouraging, because it shows that it is possible to change harmful activities, even if they are deeply entrenched. 

Other lessons can be drawn from history. I hope that the brief examples in the blog post show that we can indeed abandon the view that contemporary harms are 
new. This should be cause for optimism, because it means that we can indeed learn from our successes and failures in dealing with harms of the past.

​Please visit Justice Everywhere for the original post. 
This post is based on a paper I wrote with Derek Bell and Joanne Swaffield, and which is now published in ​Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics
0 Comments

Why we need MORE materialism

6/24/2019

0 Comments

 
As the famous adage holds, we should try to Do More With Less. We’re living in a time in which minimalism has become a movement and to Marie Kondo has become a verb. As we all know, materialism is bad for the planet and people around us, but in this blog post for Justice Everywhere, I  only focus on how self-interest might also be a significant motivator to reduce our materialism, and also give a humble suggestion as to what fundamentally underlies moving to Doing More With Less (or getting even better at it if you’re already on the programme).

Consumerism is not making us happy, because it tries to fill up the bottomless depths of the Empty Self, we have a relentless desire for more and new stuff, even though this will only satisfy us for a moment. Research has shown time and again that beyond the point of subsistence needs, material wealth has little relationship with wellbeing. Materialistic values are associated with a pervasive undermining of people's personal wellbeing. Consumerism leads to consumer anxiety, work stress,  and materialistic pursuits thwart other pursuits and other sources of life satisfaction, the most important of which are mainly non-material in nature: leisure, interpersonal relationships, community involvement, cultural and political participation, recognition, self-respect, and personal growth.

​In the documentary Minimalism, A documentary about the important things, influential American Professor of Sociology Juliet Schor provocatively says that we are actually not materialistic enough:

"
We are too materialistic in the everyday sense of the world. And we are not at all materialistic enough in the true sense of the word. We need to be true materialists, like really care about the materiality of goods. Instead we’re in a world in which material goods are so important for their symbolic meaning, what they do to position us in the status system based on what advertising or marketing says they’re about."

You can read the entire blog post on Justice Everywhere. 
0 Comments

My Body, My self? - #everydaylookism

6/3/2019

0 Comments

 
In this blog post for Justice Everywhere, I am not developing a new argument. Rather, I pay tribute to the work of my friend and colleague Heather Widdows's fascinating work on Beauty. She is the author of Perfect Me. Beauty as an ethical ideal (Princeton University Press, 2018).

In this video, Heather gives a very quick introduction to her main argument in ​Perfect Me:

In my blog post, I try to do two things. 

First, I summarise my take on Heather's argument very briefly, with a focus on how the beauty ideal is not all evil: it also offers pleasurable individual and communal practices; (many forms of) body work are good for us; beauty objectification can be empowering, protective, promising, and transforming; and beauty can serve some egalitarian purposes in that it shortcuts some existing power hierarchies, and erodes some harmful social features (such as class and wealth) which have traditionally structured society.

However, we will have to prevent a bleak future scenario in which the beauty ideal becomes increasingly narrow, demanding, punishing, divisive, and thus increasingly harmful. And rather nurture and facilitate the positive aspects of beauty – those that enhance, respect, connect, and cherish people. 

One of the main actions to be undertaken to this effect is to end Lookism. In our visual and virtual culture, our bodies have become our selves, and therefore when we shame bodies, we actually shame people. Negative comments about other people’s bodies cut deeply and are unacceptable prejudice. This is lookism, and it has to stop.
Picture
This brings me to the second aim of my blog post: to support and spread the #everydaylookism campaign, and to point out that ethicists and political theorists do have a role to play regarding the topic of beauty (which at first sight seems trivial and fluffy). 

Heather and her team launch the 
#everydaylookism campaign, which asks you to share your lookism experience (what it was, how it made you feel and to say it should not happen). The ultimate goals are to call out body shaming, show lookism as the prejudice it is, and end it.
Sharing these lookism experiences can also have a more immediate and intrinsic effect as well because it can be helpful in processing such negative experiences. It can be immensely important for people who have been (or are being) subjected to lookism to know that they’re not alone, and that other people (victims and non-victims alike) reject it as the prejudice it is. And it is exactly this that can empower us to end everyday lookism.

What can philosophers do? This campaign will only succeed if we all work together. One of the tasks of philosophers would be to analyse the instances of everyday lookism in order to identify possible structures and trends behind them. In addition, the data consisting of real and highly specific instances gives us a firm ground to methodically examine the prejudices involved, to report these harms in the public domain, and to influence policy. Finally, I believe that our theoretical work on collective action, structural injustice, and responsibility can inform the campaign and the steps to be undertaken to end everyday lookism.

The complete Blog Post can be read on Justice Everywhere, here. 
0 Comments

Climate ethicists flying to conferences? The middle ground regarding voluntarily offsetting emissions

9/3/2018

1 Comment

 
Voluntary offsetting allows you to ‘neutralise’ your carbon dioxide emissions by preventing the same amount of carbon dioxide from being emitted by someone else, most often somewhere else. Offsetting is a very polarised issue: some defend it as an effective way for individuals to neutralise their carbon emissions, while others have fiercely opposed it as a morally dubious practice

In this post, I take a position in the middle: I believe that under some conditions, emitting-and-offsetting should be morally acceptable. Briefly, these conditions are: 
  1. Select an independent, non-profit organisation to offset your emissions
  2. Select an organisation that is transparent about how your money is put to use and how the offsetting occurs in practice
  3. Select a project that has been verified by a certification organisation: to make it easier for you to determine whether offsetting projects satisfy the more technical requirements (such as additionality), some independent projects on their effective emission  reduction, among other criteria. For example, the Gold Standard is awarded to projects that effectively contribute to protecting the climate as well as to at least three additional Sustainable Development Goals
  4. Select projects in the developing world, with direct additional benefits for the communities involved
  5. Pay a fair price for your offsetting
  6. Do not offset lightly: offsetting remains a second-best solution, for emissions that are non-trivial and unavoidable. This at least requires you to critically reflect upon and justify the activities through which you emit the greenhouse gases to be offset.
  7. Offsetting should not lead to complacency: it does not fulfil other duties of global justice (including other duties related to tackling climate change)

On the basis of these conditions, I can recommend the following organisations to offset your emissions: 
  • MyClimate
  • Atmosfair
  • ClimateCare

I explain the reasoning behind the conditions into some more detail in the original Blog Post for Justice Everywhere. However, I feel that this already long post does not yet sufficiently explain my position, so I am thinking about writing a full paper about this. I'll keep you posted!
1 Comment

Plastic pollution: how to avoid further degrading our natural environment

6/4/2018

0 Comments

 
The theme of the 2018 World Environment Day (5 June 2018) was Beat Plastic Pollution. Plastic pollution is indeed a serious problem, severely affecting animals, humans, and ecosystems. Removal of the pollutants that are already in the environment is exceedingly difficult, so in this blog post for Justice Everywhere, I try to address the question as to how we can avoid plastic and other pollutants entering the environment in the first place?

Three variables determine environmental impact: Population, Affluence, and Technology. It is appealing to focus on only one of these variables and expect an easy-fix solution, but we should really address all three factors simultaneously.

There is not one panacea, because there are some physical, social, and ethical limits to the extent to which we can reduce the impact of each factor. Moreover, on all three dimensions, we can already take small actions, which combined already significantly reduce humanity's environmental impact. We would also have to take the three factors into account because there are some interactions between them that we should monitor.

Finally, there are a lot of ethical issues involved, such as the relation between individual actions and political institutions, gender justice, power relationships between rich and poor, and the traditional (but arbitrary and artificial) separation between private and public sphere. These issues cannot be avoided if we focus on one factor only. An integral approach is likely to do better in this respect. 

The original post for Justice Everywhere can be read here. 
0 Comments

The paris agreement on climate change: a historical landmark or an empty box?

12/16/2015

0 Comments

 
The Paris Agreement on Climate Change has been heralded as a monumental succes, but others have also already expressed strong criticism.

I agree that it does seem appropriate to call the Paris Agreement historical: the global context of power and economic inequalities notwithstanding, the countries around the globe have succeeded in reaching a unanimous, legally binding, and substantial agreement about the future of the planet. 

Nonetheless, the success of the agreement will depend on its translation into practical action and policy, and especially on the following additional factors
  • Ambition: the pledges of the individual countries have to become much more ambitious in order to be in line with the primary objective of keeping global warming below 2 degrees Celsius (and preferably below 1.5 degrees Celsius)
  • Long-term goals: the EU and most countries have mainly specified targets for 2030 and 2050. However, the lower emissions become, the more difficult further reductions will become. Therefore, I advocate that intermediate reductions should be much more substantial than current pledges. We can already do a lot with existing technologies, and the sooner and deeper emissions cuts can be made, the larger the benefits, and the more time we will have to do the harder reductions in the future. 
  • Financially assisting developing countries: people in developing countries are entitled to increasing their quality of life, but if global warming is to be reduced, they will have to do so in a sustainable way. Fairness therefore demands that developed countries increase their financial assistance to developing countries to develop in a sustainable way.

The framework set out by the Paris Agreement remains to be translated in effective action and policy measures, and I really hope that it does not remain an empty box...

Please read the original blog post on Justice Everywhere.
0 Comments

Do I make a difference?

11/9/2015

0 Comments

 
There is always much debate about what our governments and political institutions should do in order to tackle climate change. Important as this may be, I believe this focus should not obscure the role of individuals, but in the general perception as well as some accounts in climate ethics, individuals do not appear to be responsible for climate change, or have any agency in tackling it.

I believe this view is mistaken. In this series of blog posts for Justice-Everywhere, I try to address some pervasive, but (in my view) misleading assumptions regarding individual responsibility for climate change and offer some fresh arguments. I briefly summarise them here - please click on the titles to go to the original posts on Justice Everywhere.

  1. The exceedingly small but fully real effects of my greenhouse gas emissions
    It appears to be the case that an individual's emissions, taken separately, are too small to make any difference. Therefore, to many people, they seem entirely faultless. My view, however, is that even though these emissions are indeed very small, they are fully real. For example, on average, Brits emit about 6.5 tonnes of CO2 per year. These emissions are of course tiny in comparison with the billions of tonnes of CO2 emitted by everyone around the world, but they are not zero, and they are emitted in the context of a climate regulation system which is already saturated with CO2, making a tiny but fully real contribution to global warming.

  2. A threshold phenomenon? 
    Some people hold the view that global warming is a threshold phenomenon: individual emissions are neither sufficient nor necessary to cause climate change. However, I believe that this view is mistaken: there are thresholds in the climate system (for example, when the Greenland Ice Sheet disappears), but even below such thresholds, we see the detrimental consequences of climate change. Currently, the world has warmed about 1 degree Celsius since 1880, and we already see a higher frequency and intensity of extreme weather events. The only relevant threshold has been crossed when we started burning fossil fuels on a massive scale (say 200 years ago). Since then, any additional CO2 emissions have exacerbated the problem (and continue to do so), even the tiny amount of CO2 emitted by an individual. 

  3. Unilateral duties to reduce greenhouse gases or promotional duties?
    Some people believe that individuals only have the duty to promote just institutions, and not to reduce their own individual greenhouse gases. However, if an individual's emissions contribute a tiny but fully real amount to global warming (see 1 and 2), then individual actions to reduce greenhouse gas emissions (for example, taking showers instead of baths, turning off the light when you leave a room, ...) contribute to solving the problem in an equally tiny but fully real way! In addition to this, people also have duties to promote just and adequate institutions. 

  4. The agency of individuals and households
    We cannot expect people to reduce emissions that are unavoidable on the individual level, since everyone has to eat, breath and realise other basic rights. Nonetheless, there are a number of actions that individuals and households can take to reduce the emissions from their residential energy use, personal transportation, and consumption of animal products.

In sum, as Dale Jamieson's puts it so eloquently: "Biking instead of driving or choosing the veggie burger rather than the hamburger may seem like small choices, and it may seem that such small choices by such little people barely matter. But ironically, they may be the only thing that matters. For large changes are caused and constituted by small choices."​
0 Comments

    Archive

    February 2020
    July 2019
    June 2019
    September 2018
    June 2018
    December 2015
    November 2015

Powered by Create your own unique website with customizable templates.
  • Home
  • About Me
  • Research topics
  • Publications
  • Public Engagement (English)
  • Publiek Engagement (Nederlands)
  • Contact
  • Placement-based learning